If Trump v. United States has no foundation in the original meaning of the Constitution (as discussed in my last post), what is the rationale of the decision? Delahunty and Yoo make three main points in support of the majority’s ruling: (1) the holding is consistent with (if not compelled by) the Court’s reasoning in Nixon v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 731 (1982); (2) the holding is consistent with separation of powers principles; and (3) the holding is supported by public policy considerations, specifically the need to end the (allegedly) abusive prosecutions of the former president (and to prevent similar actions in the future). To a significant extent, these justifications amount to different ways of saying the same thing. Today we will look at the Fitzgerald decision and whether the separation of powers/policy rationales of that case provide support for Trump.
Fitzgerald held, in a 5-4 decision, that current and former presidents enjoy absolute immunity from civil damage suits for actions taken within the “outer perimeter” of their official duties. The majority opinion by Justice Powell identified a variety of sources of law that were relevant to the issue before it. First, it noted that its prior immunity decisions “have been guided by the Constitution, federal statutes, and history.” 457 U.S. at 747. Second, “at least in the absence of explicit constitutional or congressional guidance, our immunity decisions have been informed by the common law.” Id. Third, the Court “necessarily also has weighed concerns of public policy, especially as illuminated by our history and the structure of our government.” Id. at 747-48.
The Court then suggest that the immunity analysis may be somewhat different for the president:
In the case of the President the inquiries into history and policy, though mandated independently by our cases, tend to converge. Because the Presidency did not exist through most of the development of the common law, any historical analysis must draw its evidence primarily from our constitutional heritage and structure. Historical inquiry thus merges with the kind of “public policy” analysis appropriately undertaken by a federal court. This inquiry involves policies and principles that may be considered implicit in the nature of the President’s office in a system structured to achieve effective government under a constitutionally mandated separation of powers.
457 U.S. at 748.
This is a rather word salady way of saying two things. First, the Court thinks that the president should be treated differently in the immunity analysis than other executive officials, such as cabinet officers and governors. Specifically, while the Court’s precedents called for evaluating immunity based on the particular function being performed by the official who is sued for damages, Fitzgerald found that the unique nature of the presidency required extending immunity to all conduct within the “outer perimeter” of this official responsibility. Id. at 756; see also id. at 750 (“The President’s unique status under the Constitution distinguishes him from other executive officials.”).
The second point is that the grounding of the president’s immunity in separation of powers arguably placed it beyond Congress’s power to regulate. If the Constitution mandates absolute immunity for the president, Congress would be prohibited from imposing damages liability for any conduct within the outer perimeter of his duties. However, the Fitzgerald Court declined to decide whether the president would enjoy immunity in the event Congress enacted a statute which expressly authorized civil damages against the president. See Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. at 748-49 n.27 (“our holding today need only be that the President is absolutely immune from civil damages liability for his official acts in the absence of explicit affirmative action by Congress”).
This position was criticized by both the dissenters and Chief Justice Burger in his concurrence; they agreed that it was inconsistent for the majority to both claim that the president had absolute immunity based on separation of powers, on the one hand, and to leave open whether this immunity could be abrogated by affirmative congressional action, on the other. See Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. at 792 “We are never told . . . how or why congressional action could make a difference.”) (White J., dissenting); id. at 798 (Blackmun, J., dissenting); id. at 758, 763 n.7 (Burger, C.J., concurring).
The internal correspondence of the Fitzgerald Court shows that almost all of the justices, in fact, believed that this was a contradiction, though they were sharply divided on which way it should be resolved. The four dissenting justices, of course, believed the Constitution provide no immunity, while at least two other justices in the majority privately agreed with Burger that the constitutional immunity would apply even in the face of a statute to the contrary. Powell also indicated he would agree with Burger should the issue be presented, though he fluctuated somewhat on how definite this position was. Only Justice Stevens was firmly in the undecided camp, and he evidently refused to join the majority opinion unless it clearly spelled out that affirmative congressional action would present a different case.
Personally, I can see where Stevens was coming from. Although the Fitzgerald Court states that “[w]e consider [the president’s immunity from civil damages] a functionally mandated incident of the President’s unique office, rooted in the constitutional tradition of the separation of powers and supported by our history,” 457 U.S. at 749, these buzzwords mean very little. The fact that the Court “considers” immunity to be a “functionally mandated incident of the President’s unique office” just means that it believes subjecting the president to civil damages is a bad idea that would interfere with his ability to do his job. That it is “rooted in the separation of powers” is little more than another way to refer to the president’s “unique office,” or, as the Court phrases it later, “the special nature of the President’s constitutional office and functions.” See 457 U.S. at 756. The claim that immunity is “supported by our history” appears to be mostly meaningless filler.
Indeed, Powell’s early drafts used the phrase “justified by considerations of public policy” instead of “supported by our history.” He changed this wording, and made several other edits, in response to comments from his colleagues that the draft was too forthright in acknowledging that the decision was essentially an exercise of judicial policymaking. One particularly amusing memo from Stevens expresses concern about the frequent references to public policy and descriptions of “the Executive’s immunity as something that is granted by the Court rather than provided by law.” He explained that “[i]n a realistic sense, perhaps your opinion is entirely correct in referring to grants of immunity by judges, but I feel much more comfortable when I am able to say that we are merely applying the law as we understand it to exist independently of the composition of the Court.” Powell dutifully made the cosmetic changes, but the dissent still pointed out the reality. See 457 U.S. at 769 (noting that “the judgment in this case has few, if any, indicia of a judicial decision; it is almost wholly a policy choice, a choice that is without substantial support and that in all events is ambiguous in its reach and import”) (White, J., dissenting).
Given that, in a “realistic sense,” the opinion was more of a policy choice than a judicial decision, it is understandable that Stevens insisted on reserving the question of what would happen if Congress acted to impose liability on the president. Congress is rather better suited than the Court to make a policy judgment about whether the president should be subject to civil liability. Even if one accepts that the Constitution requires the courts to balance the public interest supporting and opposing immunity, the fact of congressional action would seem to be a factor that should be considered in weighing the competing interests (a point Powell made to his skeptical colleagues in an internal memo).
It is also worth noting that the Fitzgerald Court’s rhetoric about the president’s “unique office” should be taken with a grain of salt. In a case several years earlier, Butz v. Economou, 438 U.S. 478 (1978), the Court had held by a 5-4 majority that cabinet officers and other federal officials were generally entitled only to qualified immunity in civil damage suits. The dissent, however, contended that absolute immunity should apply. Three of the four dissenters in Butz joined the majority in Fitzgerald, while four members of the Butz majority dissented in Fitzgerald. Powell was the only justice who switched sides, and thus perhaps the only one who thought the president’s unique office was determinative of the level of immunity. (Justice O’Connor, who joined the majority opinion in Fitzgerald, had not been on the Court when Butz was decided). The decision to provide absolute immunity to the president but not to cabinet officers is thus one not necessarily dictated by the reasoning of either Butz or Fitzgerald. Cf. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. at 784 (pointing out that the majority’s concerns about the chilling effect of civil lawsuits would apply to all officers, not just the president) (White, J., dissenting). Continue reading “Immunity, Impeachment and the Juristocracy (Part II: Nixon v. Fitzgerald)”